home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- SciMath FAQ
-
- Table of Contents
- -----------------
- 1Q.- Fermat's Last Theorem, status of ..
- 2Q.- Values of Record Numbers
- 3Q.- Formula for prime numbers...
- 4Q.- Digits of Pi, computation and references
- 5Q.- Odd Perfect Number
- 6Q.- Computer Algebra Systems, application of ..
- 7Q.- Computer Algebra Systems, references to ..
- 8Q.- Fields Medal, general info ..
- 9Q.- Four Colour Theorem, proof of ..
- 10Q.- 0^0=1. A comprehensive approach
- 11Q.- 0.999... = 1. Properties of the real numbers ..
- 12Q.- There are three doors, The Monty Hall problem, Master Mind and
- other games ..
- 13Q.- Surface and Volume of the n-ball
- 14Q.- f(x)^f(x)=x, name of the function ..
- 15Q.- Projective plane of order 10 ..
- 16Q.- How to compute day of week of a given date
- 17Q.- Axiom of Choice and/or Continuum Hypothesis?
- 18Q.- Cutting a sphere into pieces of larger volume
- 19Q.- Pointers to Quaternions
- 20Q.- Erdos Number
- 21Q.- Why is there no Nobel in mathematics?
- 22Q.- General References and textbooks...
- 23Q.- Interest Rate...
- 24Q.- Euler's formula e^(i Pi) = - 1 ...
-
-
-
- 6Q: I have this complicated symbolic problem (most likely
- a symbolic integral or a DE system) that I can't solve.
- What should I do?
-
- A: Find a friend with access to a computer algebra system
- like MAPLE, MACSYMA or MATHEMATICA and ask her/him to solve it.
- If packages cannot solve it, then (and only then) ask the net.
-
-
- 7Q: Where can I get <Symbolic Computation Package>?
-
- THIS IS NOT A COMPREHENSIVE LIST. There are other Computer Algebra
- packages available that may better suit your needs. There is also
- a FAQ list in the group sci.math.symbolic. It includes a much larger
- list of vendors and developers. (The FAQ list can be obtained from
- math.berkeley.edu via anonymous ftp).
-
-
-
- A: Maple
- Purpose: Symbolic and numeric computation, mathematical
- programming, and mathematical visualization.
- Contact: Waterloo Maple Software,
- 450 Phillip Street
- Waterloo, Ontario
- N2L 5J2
- Phone (519)747-2373
- FAX (519)747-5284
- email: info@maplesoft.on.ca
-
-
- A: DOE-Macsyma
- Purpose: Symbolic and mathematical manipulations.
- Contact: National Energy Software Center
- Argonne National Laboratory 9700 South Cass Avenue
- Argonne, Illinois 60439
- Phone: (708) 972-7250
-
-
- A: Pari
- Purpose: Number-theoretic computations and simple numerical
- analysis.
- Available for most 32-bit machines, including 386+387 and 486.
- This is a copyrighted but free package, available by ftp from
- math.ucla.edu (128.97.4.254) and ftp.inria.fr (128.93.1.26).
- Contact: questions about pari can be sent to pari@ceremab.u-bordeaux.fr
- and for the Macintosh versions to bernardi@mathp7.jussieu.fr
-
-
- A: Mathematica
- Purpose: Mathematical computation and visualization,
- symbolic programming.
- Contact: Wolfram Research, Inc.
- 100 Trade Center Drive Champaign,
- IL 61820-7237
- Phone: 1-800-441-MATH
- info@wri.com
-
-
- A: Macsyma
- Purpose: Symbolic numerical and graphical mathematics.
- Contact: Macsyma Inc.
- 20 Academy Street
- Arlington, MA 02174
- tel: 617-646-4550
- fax: 617-646-3161
- email: info-macsyma@macsyma.com
-
-
- A: Matlab
- Purpose: `matrix laboratory' for tasks involving
- matrices, graphics and general numerical computation.
- Contact: The MathWorks, Inc.
- 21 Prime Park Way
- Natick, MA 01760
- 508-653-1415
- info@mathworks.com
-
-
- A: Cayley
- Purpose: Computation in algebraic and combinatorial structures
- such as groups, rings, fields, modules and graphs.
- Available for: SUN 3, SUN 4, IBM running AIX or VM, DEC VMS, others
- Contact: Computational Algebra Group
- University of Sydney
- NSW 2006
- Australia
- Phone: (61) (02) 692 3338
- Fax: (61) (02) 692 4534
- cayley@maths.su.oz.au
-
-
- 8Q: Let P be a property about the Fields Medal. Is P(x) true?
-
- A: Institution is meant to be the Institution to which the researcher
- in question was associated to at the time the medal was awarded.
-
-
- Year Name Birthplace Age Institution
- ---- ---- ---------- --- -----------
- 1936 Ahlfors, Lars Helsinki Finland 29 Harvard U USA
- 1936 Douglas, Jesse New York NY USA 39 MIT USA
- 1950 Schwartz, Laurent Paris France 35 U of Nancy France
- 1950 Selberg, Atle Langesund Norway 33 Adv.Std.Princeton USA
- 1954 Kodaira, Kunihiko Tokyo Japan 39 Princeton U USA
- 1954 Serre, Jean-Pierre Bages France 27 College de France France
- 1958 Roth, Klaus Breslau Germany 32 U of London UK
- 1958 Thom, Rene Montbeliard France 35 U of Strasbourg France
- 1962 Hormander, Lars Mjallby Sweden 31 U of Stockholm Sweden
- 1962 Milnor, John Orange NJ USA 31 Princeton U USA
- 1966 Atiyah, Michael London UK 37 Oxford U UK
- 1966 Cohen, Paul Long Branch NJ USA 32 Stanford U USA
- 1966 Grothendieck, Alexander Berlin Germany 38 U of Paris France
- 1966 Smale, Stephen Flint MI USA 36 UC Berkeley USA
- 1970 Baker, Alan London UK 31 Cambridge U UK
- 1970 Hironaka, Heisuke Yamaguchi-ken Japan 39 Harvard U USA
- 1970 Novikov, Serge Gorki USSR 32 Moscow U USSR
- 1970 Thompson, John Ottawa KA USA 37 U of Chicago USA
- 1974 Bombieri, Enrico Milan Italy 33 U of Pisa Italy
- 1974 Mumford, David Worth, Sussex UK 37 Harvard U USA
- 1978 Deligne, Pierre Brussels Belgium 33 IHES France
- 1978 Fefferman, Charles Washington DC USA 29 Princeton U USA
- 1978 Margulis, Gregori Moscow USSR 32 InstPrblmInfTrans USSR
- 1978 Quillen, Daniel Orange NJ USA 38 MIT USA
- 1982 Connes, Alain Draguignan France 35 IHES France
- 1982 Thurston, William Washington DC USA 35 Princeton U USA
- 1982 Yau, Shing-Tung Kwuntung China 33 IAS USA
- 1986 Donaldson, Simon Cambridge UK 27 Oxford U UK
- 1986 Faltings, Gerd 1954 Germany 32 Princeton U USA
- 1986 Freedman, Michael Los Angeles CA USA 35 UC San Diego USA
- 1990 Drinfeld, Vladimir Kharkov USSR 36 Phys.Inst.Kharkov USSR
- 1990 Jones, Vaughan Gisborne N Zealand 38 UC Berkeley USA
- 1990 Mori, Shigefumi Nagoya Japan 39 U of Kyoto? Japan
- 1990 Witten, Edward Baltimore USA 38 Princeton U/IAS USA
-
- References :
-
- International Mathematical Congresses, An Illustrated History 1893-1986,
- Revised Edition, Including 1986, by Donald J.Alberts, G. L. Alexanderson
- and Constance Reid, Springer Verlag, 1987.
-
- Tropp, Henry S., ``The origins and history of the Fields Medal,''
- Historia Mathematica, 3(1976), 167-181.
-
-
- 9Q: Has the Four Colour Theorem been proved?
-
- Four Color Theorem:
-
- Every planar map with regions of simple borders can be coloured
- with 4 colours in such a way that no two regions sharing a non-zero
- length border have the same colour.
-
- A: This theorem was proved with the aid of a computer in 1976.
- The proof shows that if aprox. 1,936 basic forms of maps
- can be coloured with four colours, then any given map can be
- coloured with four colours. A computer program coloured this
- basic forms. So far nobody has been able to prove it without
- using a computer. In principle it is possible to emulate the
- computer proof by hand computations.
-
- References:
-
- K. Appel and W. Haken, Every planar map is four colourable,
- Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 82, 1976
- pp.711-712.
-
- K. Appel and W. Haken, Every planar map is four colourable,
- Illinois Journal of Mathematics, vol. 21, 1977, pp. 429-567.
-
- T. Saaty and Paul Kainen, The Four Colour Theorem: Assault and
- Conquest, McGraw-Hill, 1977. Reprinted by Dover Publications 1986.
-
- K. Appel and W. Haken, Every Planar Map is Four Colourable,
- Contemporary Mathematics, vol. 98, American Mathematical Society,
- 1989, pp.741.
-
- F. Bernhart, Math Reviews. 91m:05007, Dec. 1991. (Review of Appel
- and Haken's book).
-
-
- 10Q: What is 0^0 ?
-
- A: According to some Calculus textbooks, 0^0 is an "indeterminate
- form". When evaluating a limit of the form 0^0, then you need
- to know that limits of that form are called "indeterminate forms",
- and that you need to use a special technique such as L'Hopital's
- rule to evaluate them. Otherwise, 0^0=1 seems to be the most
- useful choice for 0^0. This convention allows us to extend
- definitions in different areas of mathematics that otherwise would
- require treating 0 as a special case. Notice that 0^0 is a
- discontinuity of the function x^y.
-
- Rotando & Korn show that if f and g are real functions that vanish
- at the origin and are _analytic_ at 0 (infinitely differentiable is
- not sufficient), then f(x)^g(x) approaches 1 as x approaches 0 from
- the right.
-
- From Concrete Mathematics p.162 (R. Graham, D. Knuth, O. Patashnik):
-
- "Some textbooks leave the quantity 0^0 undefined, because the
- functions x^0 and 0^x have different limiting values when x
- decreases to 0. But this is a mistake. We must define
-
- x^0 = 1 for all x,
-
- if the binomial theorem is to be valid when x=0, y=0, and/or x=-y.
- The theorem is too important to be arbitrarily restricted! By
- contrast, the function 0^x is quite unimportant."
- Published by Addison-Wesley, 2nd printing Dec, 1988.
-
- References:
-
- H. E. Vaughan, The expression '0^0', Mathematics Teacher 63 (1970),
- pp.111-112.
-
- Louis M. Rotando & Henry Korn, "The Indeterminate Form 0^0",
- Mathematics Magazine, Vol. 50, No. 1 (January 1977), pp. 41-42.
-
- L. J. Paige, A note on indeterminate forms, American Mathematical
- Monthly, 61 (1954), 189-190; reprinted in the Mathematical
- Association of America's 1969 volume, Selected Papers on Calculus,
- pp. 210-211.
-
-
- 11Q: Why is 0.9999... = 1?
-
- A: In modern mathematics, the string of symbols "0.9999..." is
- understood to be a shorthand for "the infinite sum 9/10 + 9/100
- + 9/1000 + ...." This in turn is shorthand for "the limit of the
- sequence of real numbers 9/10, 9/10 + 9/100, 9/10 + 9/100 + 9/1000,
- ..." Using the well-known epsilon-delta definition of limit, one
- can easily show that this limit is 1. The statement that
- 0.9999... = 1 is simply an abbreviation of this fact.
-
- oo m
- --- 9 --- 9
- 0.999... = > ---- = lim > ----
- --- 10^n m->oo --- 10^n
- n=1 n=1
-
-
- Choose epsilon > 0. Suppose delta = 1/-log_10 epsilon, thus
- epsilon = 10^(-1/delta). For every m>1/delta we have that
-
- | m |
- | --- 9 | 1 1
- | > ---- - 1 | = ---- < ------------ = epsilon
- | --- 10^n | 10^m 10^(1/delta)
- | n=1 |
-
- So by the (epsilon-delta) definition of the limit we have
-
- m
- --- 9
- lim > ---- = 1
- m->oo --- 10^n
- n=1
-
-
- An *informal* argument could be given by noticing that the following
- sequence of "natural" operations has as a consequence 1 = 0.9999....
- Therefore it's "natural" to assume 1 = 0.9999.....
-
- x = 0.99999....
- 10x = 9.99999....
- 10x - x = 9
- 9x = 9
- x = 1
- Thus
- 1 = 0.99999....
-
- References:
-
- E. Hewitt & K. Stromberg, Real and Abstract Analysis,
- Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1965.
-
- W. Rudin, Principles of Mathematical Analysis, McGraw-Hill, 1976.
-
-
- 12Q: There are three doors, and there is a car hidden behind one
- of them, Master Mind and other games ..
-
- A: Read frequently asked questions from rec.puzzles, as well as
- their ``archive file'' where the problem is solved and carefully
- explained. (The Monty Hall problem).
-
- MANY OTHER MATHEMATICAL GAMES ARE EXPLAINED IN THE REC.PUZZLES
- FAQ AND ARCHIVES. READ IT BEFORE ASKING IN SCI.MATH.
-
- Your chance of winning is 2/3 if you switch and 1/3 if you don't.
- For a full explanation from the rec.puzzles' archive, send to the
- address archive-request@questrel.com an email message consisting
- of the text
-
- send monty.hall
-
-
- Also any other FAQ list can be obtained through anonymous ftp from
- rtfm.mit.edu.
-
- References
-
- American Mathematical Monthly, January 1992.
-
-
- For the game of Master Mind it has been proven that no more than
- five moves are required in the worst case. For references look at
-
- One such algorithm was published in the Journal of Recreational
- Mathematics; in '70 or '71 (I think), which always solved the
- 4 peg problem in 5 moves. Knuth later published an algorithm which
- solves the problem in a shorter # of moves - on average - but can
- take six guesses on certain combinations.
-
-
-
- Donald E. Knuth, The Computer as Master Mind, J. Recreational Mathematics
- 9 (1976-77), 1-6.
-
-
- 13Q: What is the formula for the "Surface Area" of a sphere in
- Euclidean N-Space. That is, of course, the volume of the N-1
- solid which comprises the boundary of an N-Sphere.
-
- A: The volume of a ball is the easiest formula to remember: It's r^N
- times pi^(N/2)/(N/2)!. The only hard part is taking the factorial
- of a half-integer. The real definition is that x! = Gamma(x+1), but
- if you want a formula, it's:
-
- (1/2+n)! = sqrt(pi)*(2n+2)!/(n+1)!/4^(n+1)
-
- To get the surface area, you just differentiate to get
- N*pi^(N/2)/(N/2)!*r^(N-1).
-
- There is a clever way to obtain this formula using Gaussian
- integrals. First, we note that the integral over the line of
- e^(-x^2) is sqrt(pi). Therefore the integral over N-space of
- e^(-x_1^2-x_2^2-...-x_N^2) is sqrt(pi)^n. Now we change to
- spherical coordinates. We get the integral from 0 to infinity
- of V*r^(N-1)*e^(-r^2), where V is the surface volume of a sphere.
- Integrate by parts repeatedly to get the desired formula.
-
- It is possible to derive the volume of the sphere from ``first
- principles''.
-
-
- 14Q: Does anyone know a name (or a closed form) for
-
- f(x)^f(x)=x
-
-
- Solving for f one finds a "continued fraction"-like answer
-
-
- f(x) = log x
- -----
- log (log x
- ------
- ...........
-
- A: This question has been repeated here from time to time over the
- years, and no one seems to have heard of any published work on it,
- nor a published name for it (D. Merrit proposes "lx" due to its
- (very) faint resemblance to log). It's not an analytic function.
-
- The "continued fraction" form for its numeric solution is highly
- unstable in the region of its minimum at 1/e (because the graph is
- quite flat there yet logarithmic approximation oscillates wildly),
- although it converges fairly quickly elsewhere. To compute its value
- near 1/e, use the bisection method which gives good results. Bisection
- in other regions converges much more slowly than the "logarithmic
- continued fraction" form, so a hybrid of the two seems suitable.
- Note that it's dual valued for the reals (and many valued complex
- for negative reals).
-
- A similar function is a "built-in" function in MAPLE called W(x).
- MAPLE considers a solution in terms of W(x) as a closed form (like
- the erf function). W is defined as W(x)*exp(W(x))=x.
-
- An extensive treatise on the known facts of Lambert's W function
- is available for anonymous ftp at daisy.uwaterloo.ca in the
- /pub/maple/5.2/share/LambertW.ps.
-
-
-
- 15Q: Does there exist a projective plane of order 10?
-
- More precisely:
-
- Is it possible to define 111 sets (lines) of 11 points each
- such that:
-
- For any pair of points there is precisely one line containing them
- both and for any pair of lines there is only one point common to
- them both?
-
-
- A: Analogous questions with n^2 + n + 1 and n + 1 instead of 111 and 11
- have been positively answered only in case n is a prime power.
- For n=6 it is not possible, more generally if n is congruent to 1
- or 2 mod 4 and can not be written as a sum of two squares, then an
- FPP of order n does not exist. The n=10 case has been settled as not
- possible either by Clement Lam. As the "proof" took several years of
- computer search (the equivalent of 2000 hours on a Cray-1) it can be
- called the most time-intensive computer assisted single proof. The
- final steps were ready in January 1989.
-
- References
-
- R. H. Bruck and H. J. Ryser, "The nonexistence of certain finite
- projective planes," Canadian Journal of Mathematics, vol. 1 (1949),
- pp 88-93.
-
- C. Lam, Amer.Math.Monthly 98 (1991), 305-318.
-
-
- 16Q: Is there a formula to determine the day of the week, given
- the month, day and year?
-
- A: First a brief explanation: In the Gregorian Calendar, over a period
- of four hundred years, there are 97 leap years and 303 normal years.
- Each normal year, the day of January 1 advances by one; for each leap
- year it advances by two.
-
- 303 + 97 + 97 = 497 = 7 * 71
-
- As a result, January 1 year N occurs on the same day of the week as
- January 1 year N + 400. Because the leap year pattern also recurs
- with a four hundred year cycle, a simple table of four hundred
- elements, and single modulus, suffices to determine the day of the
- week (in the Gregorian Calendar), and does it much faster than all the
- other algorithms proposed. Also, each element takes (in principle)
- only three bits; the entire table thus takes only 1200 bits, or 300
- bytes; on many computers this will be less than the instructions to do
- all the complicated calculations proposed for the other algorithms.
-
- Incidental note: Because 7 does not divide 400, January 1 occurs more
- frequently on some days than others! Trick your friends! In a cycle
- of 400 years, January 1 and March 1 occur on the following days with
- the following frequencies:
-
- Sun Mon Tue Wed Thu Fri Sat
- Jan 1: 58 56 58 57 57 58 56
- Mar 1: 58 56 58 56 58 57 57
-
- Of interest is that (contrary to most initial guesses) the occurrence
- is not maximally flat.
-
- The Gregorian calendar was introduced in 1582 in parts of Europe; it was
- adopted in 1752 in Great Britain and its colonies, and on various dates
- in other countries. It replaced the Julian Calendar which has a four-year
- cycle of leap years; after four years January 1 has advanced by five days.
- Since 5 is relatively prime to 7, a table of 4 * 7 = 28 elements is
- necessary for the Julian Calendar.
-
-
- There is still a 3 day / 10,000 year error which the Gregorian calendar
- does not take. into account. At some time such a correction will have
- to be done but your software will probably not last that long :-) !
-
- Here is a standard method suitable for mental computation:
-
- A. Take the last two digits of the year.
- B. Divide by 4, discarding any fraction.
- C. Add the day of the month.
- D. Add the month's key value: JFM AMJ JAS OND
- 144 025 036 146
- E. Subtract 1 for January or February of a leap year.
- F. For a Gregorian date, add 0 for 1900's, 6 for 2000's, 4 for 1700's,
- 2 for 1800's; for other years, add or subtract multiples of 400.
- G. For a Julian date, add 1 for 1700's, and 1 for every additional
- century you go back.
- H. Add the last two digits of the year.
- I. Divide by 7 and take the remainder.
-
- Now 1 is Sunday, the first day of the week, 2 is Monday, and so on.
-
- The following formula, which is for the Gregorian calendar only, may be
- more convenient for computer programming. Note that in some programming
- languages the remainder operation can yield a negative result if given
- a negative operand, so "mod 7" may not translate to a simple remainder.
-
- W == (k + [2.6m - 0.2] - 2C + Y + [Y/4] + [C/4]) mod 7
- where [] denotes the integer floor function (round down),
- k is day (1 to 31)
- m is month (1 = March, ..., 10 = December, 11 = Jan, 12 = Feb)
- Treat Jan & Feb as months of the preceding year
- C is century (1987 has C = 19)
- Y is year (1987 has Y = 87 except Y = 86 for Jan & Feb)
- W is week day (0 = Sunday, ..., 6 = Saturday)
-
- Here the century & 400 year corrections are built into the formula.
- The [2.6m-0.2] term relates to the repetitive pattern that the 30-day
- months show when March is taken as the first month.
-
-
- References:
-
- Winning Ways by Conway, Guy, Berlekamp is supposed to have it.
-
- Martin Gardner in "Mathematical Carnival".
-
- Michael Keith and Tom Craver, "The Ultimate Perpetual Calendar?",
- Journal of Recreational Mathematics, 22:4, pp. 280-282, 19
-
- K. Rosen, "Elementary Number Theory", p. 156.
-
-
-
- 17Q: What is the Axiom of Choice? Why is it important? Why some articles
- say "such and such is provable, if you accept the axiom of choice."?
- What are the arguments for and against the axiom of choice?
-
-
- A: There are several equivalent formulations:
-
- -The Cartesian product of nonempty sets is nonempty, even
- if the product is of an infinite family of sets.
-
- -Given any set S of mutually disjoint nonempty sets, there is a set C
- containing a single member from each element of S. C can thus be
- thought of as the result of "choosing" a representative from each
- set in S. Hence the name.
-
- >Why is it important?
-
- All kinds of important theorems in analysis require it. Tychonoff's
- theorem and the Hahn-Banach theorem are examples. Indeed,
- Tychonoff's theorem is equivalent to AC. Similarly, AC is equivalent
- to the thesis that every set can be well-ordered. Zermelo's first
- proof of this in 1904 I believe was the first proof in which AC was
- made explicit. AC is especially handy for doing infinite cardinal
- arithmetic, as without it the most you get is a *partial* ordering
- on the cardinal numbers. It also enables you to prove such
- interesting general facts as that n^2 = n for all infinite cardinal
- numbers.
-
- > What are the arguments for and against the axiom of choice?
-
- The axiom of choice is independent of the other axioms of set theory
- and can be assumed or not as one chooses.
-
- (For) All ordinary mathematics uses it.
-
- There are a number of arguments for AC, ranging from a priori to
- pragmatic. The pragmatic argument (Zermelo's original approach) is
- that it allows you to do a lot of interesting mathematics. The more
- conceptual argument derives from the "iterative" conception of set
- according to which sets are "built up" in layers, each layer consisting
- of all possible sets that can be constructed out of elements in the
- previous layers. (The building up is of course metaphorical, and is
- suggested only by the idea of sets in some sense consisting of their
- members; you can't have a set of things without the things it's a set
- of). If then we consider the first layer containing a given set S of
- pairwise disjoint nonempty sets, the argument runs, all the elements
- of all the sets in S must exist at previous levels "below" the level
- of S. But then since each new level contains *all* the sets that can
- be formed from stuff in previous levels, it must be that at least by
- S's level all possible choice sets have already been *formed*. This
- is more in the spirit of Zermelo's later views (c. 1930).
-
- (Against) It has some supposedly counterintuitive consequences,
- such as the Banach-Tarski paradox. (See next question)
-
- Arguments against AC typically target its nonconstructive character:
- it is a cheat because it conjures up a set without providing any
- sort of *procedure* for its construction--note that no *method* is
- assumed for picking out the members of a choice set. It is thus the
- platonic axiom par excellence, boldly asserting that a given set
- will always exist under certain circumstances in utter disregard of
- our ability to conceive or construct it. The axiom thus can be seen
- as marking a divide between two opposing camps in the philosophy of
- mathematics: those for whom mathematics is essentially tied to our
- conceptual capacities, and hence is something we in some sense
- *create*, and those for whom mathematics is independent of any such
- capacities and hence is something we *discover*. AC is thus of
- philosophical as well as mathematical significance.
-
-
- It should be noted that some interesting mathematics has come out of an
- incompatible axiom, the Axiom of Determinacy (AD). AD asserts that
- any two-person game without ties has a winning strategy for the first or
- second player. For finite games, this is an easy theorem; for infinite
- games with duration less than \omega and move chosen from a countable set,
- you can prove the existence of a counter-example using AC. Jech's book
- "The Axiom of Choice" has a discussion.
-
- An example of such a game goes as follows.
-
- Choose in advance a set of infinite sequences of integers; call it A.
- Then I pick an integer, then you do, then I do, and so on forever
- (i.e. length \omega). When we're done, if the sequence of integers
- we've chosen is in A, I win; otherwise you win. AD says that one of
- us must have a winning strategy. Of course the strategy, and which
- of us has it, will depend upon A.
-
-
- From a philosophical/intuitive/pedagogical standpoint, I think Bertrand
- Russell's shoe/sock analogy has a lot to recommend it. Suppose you have an
- infinite collection of pairs of shoes. You want to form a set with one
- shoe from each pair. AC is not necessary, since you can define the set as
- "the set of all left shoes". (Technically, we're using the axiom of
- replacement, one of the basic axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) set theory.)
- If instead you want to form a set containing one sock from each pair of an
- infinite collection of pairs of socks, you now need AC.
-
-
- References:
-
- Maddy, "Believing the Axioms, I", J. Symb. Logic, v. 53, no. 2, June 1988,
- pp. 490-500, and "Believing the Axioms II" in v.53, no. 3.
-
- Gregory H. Moore, Zermelo's Axiom of Choice, New York, Springer-Verlag,
- 1982.
-
- H. Rubin and J. E. Rubin, Equivalents of the Axiom of Choice II,
- North-Holland/Elsevier Science, 1985.
-
- A. Fraenkel, Y. Bar-Hillel, and A. Levy, Foundations of Set Theory,
- Amsterdam, North-Holland, 1984 (2nd edition, 2nd printing), pp. 53-86.
-
-
- 18Q: Cutting a sphere into pieces of larger volume. Is it possible
- to cut a sphere into a finite number of pieces and reassemble
- into a solid of twice the volume?
-
- A: This question has many variants and it is best answered explicitly.
- Given two polygons of the same area, is it always possible to
- dissect one into a finite number of pieces which can be reassembled
- into a replica of the other?
-
- Dissection theory is extensive. In such questions one needs to
- specify
-
- (A) what a "piece" is, (polygon? Topological disk? Borel-set?
- Lebesgue-measurable set? Arbitrary?)
-
- (B) how many pieces are permitted (finitely many? countably? uncountably?)
-
- (C) what motions are allowed in "reassembling" (translations?
- rotations? orientation-reversing maps? isometries?
- affine maps? homotheties? arbitrary continuous images? etc.)
-
- (D) how the pieces are permitted to be glued together. The
- simplest notion is that they must be disjoint. If the pieces
- are polygons [or any piece with a nice boundary] you can permit
- them to be glued along their boundaries, ie the interiors of the
- pieces disjoint, and their union is the desired figure.
-
-
- Some dissection results
-
- 1) We are permitted to cut into FINITELY MANY polygons, to TRANSLATE
- and ROTATE the pieces, and to glue ALONG BOUNDARIES;
- then Yes, any two equal-area polygons are equi-decomposable.
-
- This theorem was proven by Bolyai and Gerwien independently, and has
- undoubtedly been independently rediscovered many times. I would not
- be surprised if the Greeks knew this.
-
- The Hadwiger-Glur theorem implies that any two equal-area polygons are
- equi-decomposable using only TRANSLATIONS and ROTATIONS BY 180
- DEGREES.
-
- 2) THM (Hadwiger-Glur, 1951) Two equal-area polygons P,Q are
- equi-decomposable by TRANSLATIONS only, iff we have equality of these
- two functions: PHI_P() = PHI_Q()
- Here, for each direction v (ie, each vector on the unit circle in the
- plane), let PHI_P(v) be the sum of the lengths of the edges of P which
- are perpendicular to v, where for such an edge, its length is positive
- if v is an outward normal to the edge and is negative if v is an
- inward normal to the edge.
-
-
- 3) In dimension 3, the famous "Hilbert's third problem" is:
-
- "If P and Q are two polyhedra of equal volume, are they
- equi-decomposable by means of translations and rotations, by
- cutting into finitely many sub-polyhedra, and gluing along
- boundaries?"
-
- The answer is "NO" and was proven by Dehn in 1900, just a few months
- after the problem was posed. (Ueber raumgleiche polyeder, Goettinger
- Nachrichten 1900, 345-354). It was the first of Hilbert's problems
- to be solved. The proof is nontrivial but does *not* use the axiom
- of choice.
-
- "Hilbert's Third Problem", by V.G.Boltianskii, Wiley 1978.
-
-
- 4) Using the axiom of choice on non-countable sets, you can prove
- that a solid sphere can be dissected into a finite number of
- pieces that can be reassembled to two solid spheres, each of
- same volume of the original. No more than nine pieces are needed.
-
- The minimum possible number of pieces is FIVE. (It's quite easy
- to show that four will not suffice). There is a particular
- dissection in which one of the five pieces is the single center
- point of the original sphere, and the other four pieces A, A',
- B, B' are such that A is congruent to A' and B is congruent to B'.
- [See Wagon's book].
-
- This construction is known as the "Banach-Tarski" paradox or the
- "Banach-Tarski-Hausdorff" paradox (Hausdorff did an early version of
- it). The "pieces" here are non-measurable sets, and they are
- assembled *disjointly* (they are not glued together along a boundary,
- unlike the situation in Bolyai's thm.)
- An excellent book on Banach-Tarski is:
-
- "The Banach-Tarski Paradox", by Stan Wagon, 1985, Cambridge
- University Press.
-
- Robert M. French, The Banach-Tarski theorem, The Mathematical
- Intelligencer 10 (1988) 21-28.
-
-
- The pieces are not (Lebesgue) measurable, since measure is preserved
- by rigid motion. Since the pieces are non-measurable, they do not
- have reasonable boundaries. For example, it is likely that each piece's
- topological-boundary is the entire ball.
-
- The full Banach-Tarski paradox is stronger than just doubling the
- ball. It states:
-
- 5) Any two bounded subsets (of 3-space) with non-empty interior, are
- equi-decomposable by translations and rotations.
-
- This is usually illustrated by observing that a pea can be cut up
- into finitely pieces and reassembled into the Earth.
-
- The easiest decomposition "paradox" was observed first by Hausdorff:
-
- 6) The unit interval can be cut up into COUNTABLY many pieces which,
- by *translation* only, can be reassembled into the interval of
- length 2.
-
- This result is, nowadays, trivial, and is the standard example of a
- non-measurable set, taught in a beginning graduate class on measure
- theory.
-
-
- References:
-
- In addition to Wagon's book above, Boltyanskii has written at least
- two works on this subject. An elementary one is:
-
- "Equivalent and equidecomposable figures"
-
- in Topics in Mathematics published by D.C. HEATH AND CO., Boston. It
- is a translation from the 1956 work in Russian.
-
- Also, the article "Scissor Congruence" by Dubins, Hirsch and ?,
- which appeared about 20 years ago in the Math Monthly, has a pretty
- theorem on decomposition by Jordan arcs.
-
-
- ``Banach and Tarski had hoped that the physical absurdity of this
- theorem would encourage mathematicians to discard AC. They were
- dismayed when the response of the math community was `Isn't AC great?
- How else could we get such counterintuitive results?' ''
-
-
-
- Copyright Notice
-
- Copyright (c) 1993 A. Lopez-Ortiz
-
- This FAQ is Copyright (C) 1994 by Alex Lopez-Ortiz. This text,
- in whole or in part, may not be sold in any medium, including,
- but not limited to electronic, CD-ROM, or published in print,
- without the explicit, written permission of Alex Lopez-Ortiz.
-
-
-
-
- --------------------------------------------------------------------------
- Questions and Answers Edited and Compiled by:
-
- Alex Lopez-Ortiz alopez-o@maytag.UWaterloo.ca
- Department of Computer Science University of Waterloo
- Waterloo, Ontario Canada
- --
- Alex Lopez-Ortiz alopez-o@neumann.UWaterloo.ca
- Department of Computer Science University of Waterloo
- Waterloo, Ontario Canada
-